“Intentions” in Avicenna’s Psychology and Its Role in Forming the Methodic Experience and Empirical Knowledge

Document Type : Scholarly Article

Author

Assistant Professor, Department of Islamic Philosophy, The Iranian Institute of Philosophy, Tehran, Iran.

Abstract

Since Avicenna considers the main function of the estimative faculty to be the apprehension of intentions (maʿānī), other functions of this faculty must be understood in light of this form of apprehension. His primary and well-known meaning of intention is something inherently non-sensible that nonetheless exists within the particular sensibles. These intentions can generally be categorized under the duality of agreeableness (muwāfaqa) and disagreeableness (muẖālafa). Thus, a connection can be established between this class of intentions and particular accidents of existent qua existent. However, intentions never lose their relational aspect to the sensibles neither in the actualization nor in conceptualization. Avicenna also considers another kind of intention apprehended by estimation. This type of intention is nothing but the relation among the sensible forms, which is perceived from the external sensible objects and entities. Although this intention is non-sensible, unlike the first type, it is derived from and reducible to sensibles. Based on this second kind of intention, one can explain how, in estimative propositions (wahmiyyāt), judgments about sensibles are generalized to non-sensible objects. Furthermore, this generalization, if applied to the sensibles and their attributes, leads to the formation of induction. Given that Avicenna considers methodic experience (tajriba) to be the result of the conjunction between sensory induction and syllogism, it can be concluded that the estimative faculty and its apprehended intentions play a central role in the formation of empirical method and knowledge.

Keywords

Main Subjects


Ahmadi Saʿdi, Abbas 2006. Philosophical Secondary Intelligibles from the Viewpoint of Peripatetic Philosophers. Theological-Doctrinal Research, 1(3), 51-66.
Black, D. L. (1993). Estimation (Wahm) in Avicenna: The Logical and Psychological Dimensions. Dialogue, 32(2), 219–258. doi:10.1017/S0012217300014414.
Black, D.L. (2000). Imagination and Estimation: Arabic Paradigms and Western Transformations. Topoi, 19(1), 59–75. doi:10.1023/A:1006399407731.
Fadaei, Roohollah (2022). Experience(Experiment) and Its Rational Foundations in Galen and Avicenna (Ph.D Thesis). retrievable from Iran Treasure of Scientific and Technical Information (Ganj), IranDoc (No. d27764775975bb83e18e897d84f).
Fadaei, Roohollah, & Saeedimehr, Mohammad (2022). Avicenna and the Kind of “Certainty” Obtained by Experience; a New Reading. Avecinnian Philosophy Journal, 25(66), 33-51. doi: 10.30497/ap.2021.241690.1552.
Hasse, D. N. (2000). Avicenna's De Anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul 1160-1300. Italy: Warburg Institute.
Ibn Sīnā (Avicenna) (1908a). Fī Ithbāt al-Nubuwwāt wa Taʾwīl Rumuzihim wa ʾAmthālihim. In Tisʿ Risālāt fi-l-Ḥikma wa-l-Tabīʿiyyat. Cairo: Dar al-Arab.
___ (1952a). ʾAḥwāl al-Nafs. Cairo: Dar Ihyaʾ al-Kutub al-Arabiyya.
___ (1952b). Al-Shifāʾ- al-Manṭiq (al-Madkhal). Cairo: Al-Matbaʿa al-Amiriyya.
___ (1952c). Mabḥathun ʿan al-Quwā al-Nafsāniyya. In ʾAḥwāl al-Nafs. Cairo: Dar Ihyaʾ al-Kutub al-Arabiyya.
___ (1956). Al-Shifāʾ- al-Manṭiq (al- Burhān). Cairo: Wizara al-Tarbiya wa-l-Taʿlim
___ (1960). Al-Shifāʾ al-ʾIlāhiyyat. Cairo: al-Hayʾa al-Amma li Shuʾun al-Matabiʿ al-Amiriyya.
___ (1974). Al-Shifāʾ- al-Ṭabīʿiyyāt (al-Nafs). Cairo: al-Hayʾa al-Misriyya al-Amma li-l-Kitab.
___ (1980). ʿUyūn al-Ḥikma. Beirut: Dar al-Qalam.
___ (1984). Al-Mabdaʾ wa-l-Maʿād. Tehran: Muassisih-yi Mutaliat-i Islami.
___ (2000). Al-Najāt min al-Gharq fī Baḥr al-Ḍalālāt. Tehran: University of Tehran.
___ (2004a). Dānishnamih-yi ʿAlāʾī- Risālih-yi Manṭiq. Hamedan: Danishgah-i Bu-ali wa Anjuman-i Athar wa Mafakhir-i Farhangi.
___ (2004b). Risālih-yi Nafs. Hamedan: Danishgah-i Bu-ali wa Anjuman-i Athar wa Mafakhir-i Farhangi.
___ (2007). Al-Qānūn fi-l-Ṭibb (al-Kitab al-ʾAwwal). Kashan: Mursal.
___ (2012). Al-Taʿlīqāt. Tehran: Muassisiyih-yi Pazhuhishi-yi Hikmat wa Falsafi-yi Iran.
___ (2017). Al-Mukhtaṣar al-ʾAwsaṭ fi-l-Manṭiq. Tehran: Muassisiyih-yi Pazhuhishi-yi Hikmat wa Falsafi-yi Iran.
___ . Risāla fīʾUṣūl ʿIlm al-Burhān. Ahmad Thalith, 3447. Manuscript Dating: 1461. Manuscript Features in: Al-Makhtutat al-Arabiyya fi Maktaba Tub Qabi Sarayi bi Istanbul, p. 418.
___ (2002). Al-Ishārāt wa-l-Tanbihāt. Qom: Bustan-i Kitab.
____ (1908b). Fī Quwa al-ʾInsāniyya wa ʾIdrākātuha. In Tisʿ Risālāt fi-l-Ḥikma wa-l-Tabīʿiyyat. Cairo: Dar al-Arab.
Kaukua, J. (2014). Avicenna on the Soul’s Activity in Perception. In: Silva, J., Yrjönsuuri, M. (eds) Active Perception in the History of Philosophy. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04361-6_6.
McGinnis, John (2018). Experimental Thoughts on Thought Experiments in Medieval Islam. In Michael T Stuart, Yiftach Fehige, James Robert Brown (eds) The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London and New York: Routledge.
Perler, Dominik (2012). Why is the Sheep Afraid of the Wolf? Medieval Debates on Animal Passions. In Martin Pickavé, and Lisa Shapiro (eds), Emotion and Cognitive Life in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Great Britain: Oxford.
Shanazari, Jafar, & Enshaei, Mahdi (2010). Ontology of Second Contemplative Sciences of Philosophy Metaphysics, 2(5), 87-104.